nerohacker.blogg.se

Earman and norton 1998
Earman and norton 1998












earman and norton 1998 earman and norton 1998

The Earman–Norton version of the argument may be put as follows. Since then, hundreds of papers have appeared responding to the Earman–Norton argument, and much of the subsequent literature in the foundations of general relativity and elsewhere in philosophy of physics has been shaped by these debates. Footnote 4 Soon after, Norton, working now in collaboration with John Earman, argued that Einstein’s argument could be reconstructed in a way that was still relevant to contemporary debates in philosophy of physics, as a Leibniz-inspired reductio of a metaphysical conviction in the reality of spacetime points that they dubbed “manifold substantivalism”. Meanwhile, John Earman was working on the bearing of Leibniz’s thinking on a similar view, following some early thinking of Howard Stein. Working independently following this discovery, Stachel Footnote 3 and Norton argued that Einstein’s Entwurf theory and hole argument were not trivial blunders, but the result of deeper metaphysical convictions according to which, “point events of the spacetime manifold are incorrectly thought of as individuated independently of the field itself” Norton (, 256).

#Earman and norton 1998 archive#

Norton and John Statchel in the Einstein Archive at Princeton, miscatalogued as lecture notes from the University of Zurich. This simple perspective on the hole argument changed following a remarkable event in the history of science: the discovery of Einstein’s notebook of scratchpad calculations during those crucial years. In the Entwurf theory the preferred coordinate system arose in the description of a Newtonian limit, and in the hole argument it arose in the explicit expression of the metric. Over the subsequent decades, the hole argument would reappear in the work of various groups on quantum gravity, usually together with a standard story: Einstein’s 1913 blunder was a failure to realise that he had chosen a preferred coordinate system, and so he prematurely rejected general covariance. Footnote 1 But by the end of 1915, he had rejected the hole argument and the Entwurf theory, in part because he had found general relativity. In 1913, Einstein presented the hole argument in an effort to show that there could be no adequate “generally covariant” or diffeomorphism-invariant theory of gravity, instead advocating his erroneous Entwurf field equations. The history of the subject is perhaps well-known, but worth repeating. New York: HarperCollins, 1997.Few topics in the philosophy of physics have received more attention in the past forty years than Einstein’s hole argument. Religion and Science: Historical and Contemporary Issues. Vatican City State: Vatican Observatory Publications, 1999.ħ. Quantum Cosmology and the Laws of Nature: Scientific Perspectives on Divine Action, 2nd ed. Vatican City State: Vatican Observatory, 1995.Ħ. Physics, Philosophy and Theology: A common Quest for Understanding, 2nd ed. Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. Philosophy of Science: The Central Issues. Washington D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1997.Ģ. The Modeling of Nature: Philosophy of Science and Philosophy of Nature in Synthesis.














Earman and norton 1998